So I'm going to talk about trust, and I'm going to start by reminding you of the standard views that people have about trust. I think these are so commonplace, they've become clichés of our society. And I think there are three. One's a claim: there has been a great decline in trust, very widely believed. The second is an aim: we should have more trust. And the third is a task: we should rebuild trust.
I think that the claim, the aim and the task are all
misconceived. So what I'm going to try to tell you today is a different story
about a claim, an aim and a task which I think give one quite a lot better
purchase on the matter.
First the claim: Why do people think trust has declined? And
if I really think about it on the basis of my own evidence, I don't know the
answer. I'm inclined to think it may have declined in some activities or some
institutions and it might have grown in others. I don't have an overview. But,
of course, I can look at the opinion polls, and the opinion polls are
supposedly the source of a belief that trust has declined. When you actually
look at opinion polls across time, there's not much evidence for that. That's
to say, the people who were mistrusted 20 years ago, principally journalists
and politicians, are still mistrusted. And the people who were highly trusted
20 years ago are still rather highly trusted: judges, nurses. The rest of us
are in between, and by the way, the average person in the street is almost
exactly midway. But is that good evidence? What opinion polls record is, of
course, opinions. What else can they record? So they're looking at the generic
attitudes that people report when you ask them certain questions. Do you trust
politicians? Do you trust teachers?
Now if somebody said to you, "Do you trust
greengrocers? Do you trust fishmongers? Do you trust elementary school
teachers?" you would probably begin by saying, "To do what?" And
that would be a perfectly sensible response. And you might say, when you
understood the answer to that, "Well, I trust some of them, but not
others." That's a perfectly rational thing. In short, in our real lives,
we seek to place trust in a differentiated way. We don't make an assumption
that the level of trust that we will have in every instance of a certain type
of official or office-holder or type of person is going to be uniform. I might,
for example, say that I certainly trust a certain elementary school teacher I
know to teach the reception class to read, but in no way to drive the school
minibus. I might, after all, know that she wasn't a good driver. I might trust
my most loquacious friend to keep a conversation going but not -- but perhaps
not to keep a secret. Simple.
So if we've got those evidence in our ordinary lives of the
way that trust is differentiated, why do we sort of drop all that intelligence
when we think about trust more abstractly? I think the polls are very bad
guides to the level of trust that actually exists, because they try to
obliterate the good judgment that goes into placing trust.
Secondly, what about the aim? The aim is to have more trust.
Well frankly, I think that's a stupid aim. It's not what I would aim at. I
would aim to have more trust in the trustworthy but not in the untrustworthy.
In fact, I aim positively to try not to trust the untrustworthy. And I think,
of those people who, for example, placed their savings with the very aptly
named Mr. Madoff, who then made off with them, and I think of them, and I
think, well, yes, too much trust. More trust is not an intelligent aim in this
life. Intelligently placed and intelligently refused trust is the proper aim.
Well once one says that, one says, yeah, okay, that means that what matters in
the first place is not trust but trustworthiness. It's judging how trustworthy
people are in particular respects.
And I think that judgment requires us to look at three
things. Are they competent? Are they honest? Are they reliable? And if we find
that a person is competent in the relevant matters, and reliable and honest,
we'll have a pretty good reason to trust them, because they'll be trustworthy.
But if, on the other hand, they're unreliable, we might not. I have friends who
are competent and honest, but I would not trust them to post a letter, because
they're forgetful. I have friends who are very confident they can do certain
things, but I realize that they overestimate their own competence. And I'm very
glad to say, I don't think I have many friends who are competent and reliable
but extremely dishonest. (Laughter) If so, I haven't yet spotted it.
But that's what we're looking for: trustworthiness before
trust. Trust is the response. Trustworthiness is what we have to judge. And, of
course, it's difficult. Across the last few decades, we've tried to construct
systems of accountability for all sorts of institutions and professionals and
officials and so on that will make it easier for us to judge their
trustworthiness. A lot of these systems have the converse effect. They don't
work as they're supposed to. I remember I was talking with a midwife who said,
"Well, you see, the problem is it takes longer to do the paperwork than to
deliver the baby." And all over our public life, our institutional life,
we find that problem, that the system of accountability that is meant to secure
trustworthiness and evidence of trustworthiness is actually doing the opposite.
It is distracting people who have to do difficult tasks, like midwives, from
doing them by requiring them to tick the boxes, as we say. You can all give
your own examples there.
So so much for the aim. The aim, I think, is more
trustworthiness, and that is going to be different if we are trying to be
trustworthy and communicate our trustworthiness to other people, and if we are
trying to judge whether other people or office-holders or politicians are
trustworthy. It's not easy. It is judgment, and simple reaction, attitudes,
don't do adequately here.
Now thirdly, the task. Calling the task rebuilding trust, I
think, also gets things backwards. It suggests that you and I should rebuild
trust. Well, we can do that for ourselves. We can rebuild a bit of
trustworthiness. We can do it two people together trying to improve trust. But
trust, in the end, is distinctive because it's given by other people. You can't
rebuild what other people give you. You have to give them the basis for giving
you their trust. So you have to, I think, be trustworthy. And that, of course,
is because you can't fool all of the people all of the time, usually. But you
also have to provide usable evidence that you are trustworthy. How to do it?
Well every day, all over the place, it's being done by ordinary people, by
officials, by institutions, quite effectively. Let me give you a simple commercial
example. The shop where I buy my socks says I may take them back, and they
don't ask any questions. They take them back and give me the money or give me
the pair of socks of the color I wanted. That's super. I trust them because
they have made themselves vulnerable to me. I think there's a big lesson in
that. If you make yourself vulnerable to the other party, then that is very
good evidence that you are trustworthy and you have confidence in what you are
saying. So in the end, I think what we are aiming for is not very difficult to
discern. It is relationships in which people are trustworthy and can judge when
and how the other person is trustworthy.
So the moral of all this is, we need to think much less
about trust, let alone about attitudes of trust detected or mis-detected by
opinion polls, much more about being trustworthy, and how you give people
adequate, useful and simple evidence that you're trustworthy.
Thanks
(Applause)
Thanks
(Applause)
No comments:
Post a Comment